We can see this clearly if we look at the rituals and
customs of family life. Consider what happens when you lay the table for a
meal. This is not just a utilitarian event. If you treat it as such, the ritual
will disintegrate, and the family members will end up grabbing individual
portions to eat on their own. The table is laid according to precise rules of
symmetry, choosing the right cutlery, the right plates, the right jugs and
glasses. Everything is meticulously controlled by aesthetic norms, and those
norms convey some of the meaning of family life. The pattern on a
willow-pattern plate, for example, has been fixed over centuries, and speaks of
tranquillity, of gentleness and of things that remain forever the same. Very
many ordinary objects on the table have been, as it were, polished by domestic
affection. Their edges have been rubbed off, and they speak in subdued,
unpretentious tones of belonging. Serving the food is ritualized too, and you
witness in the family meal the continuity of manners and aesthetic values. You
witness another continuity too, between aesthetic values and the emotion that
the Romans knew as piety—the recognition that the world is in other than human
hands. Hence the gods are present at mealtimes, and Christians precede their
eating with a grace, inviting God to sit down among them before they sit down
themselves.
That example tells us a lot about aesthetic judgement and
the pursuit of beauty. In particular, it shows the centrality of beauty to
home-building, and therefore to establishing a shared environment.
When the motive of sharing arises, we look for norms and conventions that we
can all accept. We leave behind our private appetites and subjective
preferences, in order to achieve a consensus that will provide a public
background to what we are and what we do. In such circumstances aesthetic
disagreements are not comfortable disagreements like disagreements over taste
in food (which are not so much disagreements as differences). When it comes to
the built environment we should not be surprised that aesthetic disagreements
are the subjects of fierce litigation and legislative enforcement—even here in
America, where each person is sovereign in his land.
We can reject the assumption that beauty is merely
subjective without embracing the view that it is objective. The distinction
between subjective and objective is neither clear nor exhaustive. I prefer to
say that judgements of beauty express rational preferences, about matters in
which the agreement of others is both sought and valued. They are not so very
different, in those respects, from moral judgements, and often concern similar
themes—as when we criticize works of art for their obscenity, cruelty, or
sentimentality. Just how far we can go down the path of rational discussion
depends upon what we think of the second assumption, namely, that beauty
doesn’t matter.
Roger Scruton, from "The High Cost of Ignoring Beauty"
No comments:
Post a Comment